Examining The Legacy Of Tony Judt
The Article: Tony Judt: A Cooler Look by Dylan Riley in the New Left Review.
The Text: Accolades continue to be piled upon the historian Tony Judt, following his untimely death in August 2010. For the Guardian, he was âa fearless critic of narrow orthodoxiesâ, âa great historianâ, âa brilliant political commentatorâ. For the New York Review of Books, âa source of inspirationâ, who sought to âembrace differenceâââlike Isaiah Berlinââwithin historical accounts that were âharmonious, convincing, and trueâ; like Camus, Blum and Aron, Judt knew what it was to bear the intellectualâs âburden of responsibilityâ. To the Economist, he was âerudite and far-sightedâ, âa meticulous intellectâââan intellectual with a capital Iâ. More circumspectly, the New York Times saluted his âdeep suspicion of left-wing ideologuesâ. In June 2011 a Paris conference, jointly organized by the NYRB and ceri SciencesPo, celebrated Judtâs âscholarly rigour, elegance of style and acuteness of judgementâ. Morally, he was âfearlessâ, âpropheticâ, a new Orwell; intellectually, he was âformidableâ, possessed of a âforceful lucidityâ; as a historian of French political life, happily âinoculated against the revolutionary ideas that had been the stock in trade of the intellectual engagĂ©â. To what extent are these plaudits confirmed by a sober examination of Judtâs work, held to the normal scholarly standards of intellectual coherence and empirical plausibility? What follows will offer an evaluation of his writings, as the necessary precondition for an adequate assessment of his contribution as historian, publicist and scholar.
Tony Judt was born in 1948, the son of Jewish immigrants, and brought up in lower-middle-class circumstances in Londonâs south-west suburbs. âComing from that branch of East European Jewry that had embraced social democracyâ, he would explain, âmy own family was viscerally anti-Communist.â Educated at a small South London private school, he served as national secretary of a Labour Zionist youth organization before going up to Kingâs College, Cambridge in 1967. Post-graduate study took him to the Ecole Normale SupĂ©rieure in Paris, where he seems to have acquired his life-long distaste for Marxist intellectuals; and thence to southern France, where he undertook doctoral research on the history of French socialism in the Var. His first two books would draw extensively on this work: La Reconstruction du Parti Socialiste, 1921â1926 was published in Paris in 1976; Socialism in Provence, 1871â1914, a âstudy in the origins of the French leftâ, appeared three years later. The mid-70s was a time of heightened establishment concern in France at the prospect of a joint SocialistâPCF election victory, in the aftermath of the Portuguese revolution. This background informs the central preoccupation in both Judtâs books with why France had failed to produce a reliable social-democratic party, on the Anglo-Nordic model. Unlike its solidly anti-Communist counterparts, the British Labour Party or German sdp, the Section Française de lâInternationale OuvriĂšre (SFIO) had never quite shed the lexicon of Marxism and still appealed to a notion of socialism even after 1945, when its political practice was otherwise quite âacceptableâ. The themes of his doctoral research would prove to be central to much of Judtâs subsequent career.
1. THE FRENCH LEFT
Judtâs first book, The Reconstruction of the Socialist Party, examined the re-establishment of the SFIO after its historic split at the 1920 Congress of Tours, where a large majority of the delegates had opted for the Third International and moved to found the Parti Communiste Française. In Judtâs view, it was the presence of a militant PCF to its left that forced the SFIO leadership to compensate for its reformist political practice with verbal commitments to socialism. The SFIO rank and file insisted that the party âremain what they had made itâ; any attempts to dilute its message would have played into the hands of the PCF. As Judt put it:
The way was narrow: a too marked rapprochement with the PCF could allow the more radical and rigid party to destroy it, but too sharp a break from the communists could lead to the loss of elements who had remained in the SFIO only on the condition that it retained a revolutionary Marxist position.
The 1920 split had not cleanly separated reformists from revolutionaries, as happened in other northern European socialist parties after the Bolshevik Revolution; instead, a section of the left remained with the rump SFIO led by LĂ©on Blum, constituting a majority of its membership. Apart from a small, right-wing faction, all the SFIO delegates rejected collaboration in bourgeois governments and advocated the dictatorship of the proletariat. Judt reported that Socialist mayors were obliged to get party approval before inaugurating Monuments to the Fallen, a sharply divisive issue for the party in the aftermath of the Great War. The SFIO leadership initially hung back from rejoining the reconstituted Second International, preferring to support the Union of Vienna, the â2.5 Internationalâ established by the Austro-Marxists, although it duly signed up in 1923. Rank-and-file attitudes exercised a decisive restraint on the SFIOâs parliamentary leadership: in 1924 Blum and his fellow deputies were obliged to lend only external support to the Radical government under Edouard Herriotâas it pursued a programme of austerity at home, imperial war in Morocco and military occupation in the Ruhrâsince the party membership would not tolerate full participation. Here was an example of the high price paid by the SFIO for the ideological ârigidityâ necessary for its survival, given the ever-present pressure from the left exercised by the PCF.
The Reconstruction of the Socialist Party was rapturously received in liberal-Atlanticist circles in France, where it was published by the National Political Science Foundation with a fulsome preface by the ex-Communist Annie Kriegel, whom even Judt was later to describe as having gone from âfull-blooded party dogma to conservative anti-Communismâ. Its warnings of the baneful effect of the PCF had obvious lessons for those tempted by the Union of the Left in the mid-70s. Anti-Communism had been the standard ideology in the Anglophone world all through the Cold War; but in France it only really became a doxa in the mid-70s. Solzhenitsynâs Gulag Archipelago was translated in 1974 and François Furetâs influential Rethinking the French Revolution was published in 1978. In this context, Judtâs hostile account of the PCFâs influence in the 1920s was the perfect calling card; a long-existent Anglo-American anti-Communism converged felicitously with a rising French one.
Judtâs second book, Socialism in Provence, 1871â1914, tracked back to a time before the baneful influence of the Comintern had been felt, aiming to rescue a vision of the modern French left as âneither a victime du marxisme nor the latest in a succession of crypto-Jacobinsâ. Drawing again on his doctoral research in the Var, Judt argued that the areas of late-nineteenth-century Socialist success were districts where small peasant proprietors were predominant, rather than sharecroppers or day labourers. The collapse of agricultural prices in the last decades of the nineteenth century had radicalized this layer. Picking up on Eric Wolfâs idea of the âmiddle peasantâ, Judt suggested that their relative economic autonomy gave small proprietors the capacity for independent action, while their vulnerability to market conjunctures, especially after the turn to viniculture, made them supporters of state protection for agriculture. Early Socialist programmes spoke directly to smallholder interests; initially, the Var peasants were âresponding to an ideology which appealed to them in class termsâ in lending the party their support. Subsequently, this attachment would congeal into an unbreakable political tradition: âvoting for the Socialists formed part of the âhistoricalâ character of Provençal life, long after the SFIO had ceased to perform any obvious function on behalf of the local population and had indeed lost much of its revolutionary character and programme.â In sum, material interests explained the rise of socialism, culture its perdurance.
As a work of empirical scholarship Socialism in Provence towers over Judtâs later output, its extensively documented analysis revealing a careful social historian. The last chapters turn towards a more general discussion of French politics and the peasantry. Judtâs argument here is a familiar one: the persistence of a broadly Marxian socialism in France was due to the large number of peasant smallholders, combined with the early introduction of universal suffrage: both legacies of the French Revolution. Franceâs backwardness, far from being a disadvantage for socialism in France, explained why it had done so relatively well. Judt gave a nod to modernization theory, agreeing that âthe potential for revolutionâ is greatest âin the early years of capitalist developmentâ. But its explanation was limited in the French case, because socialism did not disappear as the country modernized. Overall, however, the story was clear: French socialism rested above all on a peasant base, and as such was a consequence of economic backwardness.
In Furetâs footsteps
In an unguarded moment, Judt himself would remark that âat some point between 1973 and 1978 Marxism, and the study of its theoretical implications and resonances, lost its stranglehold upon the intellectual imagination in France, a grip it had exercised unbroken for a generation. In the space of less than a decade it became fashionable to be not just non-Marxist, but anti-Marxist.â Indeed; both his early works chimed perfectly with the dominant Parisian mood. Judtâs next bookâhe was ensconced, from 1980 to 1987, at St. Anneâs College, Oxford as a ppe tutorâwas also well-angled to catch this favourable wind. Published in 1986, Marxism and the French Left was Judtâs first foray into intellectual history. It had an unusual structure, to say the least: dense chapters on the nineteenth-century labour movement and the fortunes of the SFIO from 1920â36 were followed by a highly polemical presentation of French Marxism during the trente glorieuses of 1945â75, topped off by a paean to Mitterrandâs victory in 1981.
Linking these apparently disparate topics is a highly selective narrative of the French left, occluding the anti-Nazi Resistanceâindeed, dispensing with any analysis of the PCF. An ostentatiously partisan tone and a marked decline in scholarship set Marxism and the French Left apart from Judtâs earlier work; it also suffered from a notable deterioration in internal coherence, as Judt attempted to put forward two mutually contradictory arguments in the same breath. On the one hand Marxism and the French Left claimed, following Furet, that the French left had historically been blighted by an adherence to ârevolutionary doctrinesâ, with little countervailing experience of Anglo-Saxon liberties. During the course of the nineteenth century, post-1789 republican traditions had segued into Marxian ones, facilitated by the overlap of the two between the 1860s and the 1930s. On the other hand, Judt informed his readers that it was only after 1945 that âconsistently critical attitudes to capitalismâ had taken hold on the French left, though mercifully âtheir hegemony has been brief; in the 1980s it is again no longer a requirement of the left that it condemn profit, economic exploitation and wealthâ, as Mitterrandâs presidency had shown.
The explanation that Judt had confidently offered for the persistence of the revolutionary tradition in his earlier works isâjust as confidentlyâreversed, without a word of explanation, in Marxism and the French Left. In 1979 Socialism in Provence had depicted nineteenth-century France as an economically backward society, with a precociously developed state. In 1986 Marxism and the French Left presented it as an economically developed society with a backward, âilliberalâ state:
France was an industrial society with all the characteristic industrial landscapingâmassive conurbations (Lille-Roubaix-Tourcoing, St Etienne), fast-growing metropolitan cities (Paris, of course, but also Marseilles, which grew from 185,000 to 315,000 during Louis NapolĂ©onâs reign), gross extremes of wealth and poverty.
In promoting mid-nineteenth-century France to the rank of a fully industrialized society, Judt directly contradicted his previous account of the strength of French socialism being due to its anchorage in pre-industrial soil. Without ever mentioning this, he now offered a new explanation for the persistence of the revolutionary tradition: the repressiveness of the Second Empire. After the massacre of the workers in 1848, the French labour movement no longer saw the state as a neutral arbiter of class conflicts but rather as an instrument that âwould always be used at the expense of the working populationâ. The French, then, had never experienced âthat political liberalization which so confounded observers and protagonists after 1848 in other countries.â
The chapter on the inter-war experience of the SFIO in Marxism and the French Left similarly recasts, without explanation, Judtâs earlier analysis in Reconstruction of the Socialist Party. Even after the split at the Congress of Tours, in which the PCF hived off most of the industrial working-class members, leaving the SFIO as a cross-class, regional party, Socialist leaders continued to stress extra-parliamentary agitation: âfor Blum, almost as much as for the party left, elections were a means to spread the socialist word, and only secondarily did they serve to elect men to parliament, or even a local councilâ. Whereas Judt earlier suggested that the reasons for the SFIOâs failure to become a responsible social-democratic party lay in the existence of the PCF, he now argued that both the SFIO and the PCF were rooted in a common political culture, tainted by ârevolutionary doctrineââmuch more in line with Furetâs thinking.
Marxism and the French Leftâs discussion of the post-war intellectual sceneâJudtâs first stab at Sartreâwas strangely sandwiched between this chapter on the SFIO and another on Mitterrand. It asked why it was that French Marxism, backward in comparison to its German and Italian counterparts up until the 1930s, had flowered in the post-war period and then collapsed. According to Judt, this arc reflected the political strength of the PCF, whose attraction for the intelligentsia simply reflected the prestige of Stalin. âAs a theory of radical politicsâ, he declared, âMarxism died with Stalinâ. The argument fails the elementary test of chronology: the two greatest products of post-war French Marxism, Sartreâs Critique of Dialectical Reason and Althusserâs Reading Capital, were published in 1960 and 1968, respectively. As intellectual history, this was crude and shoddy stuff, not least because of Judtâs relentlessly polemical intentâCommunism, Marxism and Stalinism predictably presented as interchangeable terms. Judt made no attempt to reconstruct the ideas of post-war French thinkers, instead flaunting the fact that he had been âselectiveâ in his treatment and that his approach had been to deny them any âintellectual autonomyâ; why should anyone take Sartre, for example, âvery seriouslyâ? With protocols like this, it is not surprising that Judtâs account was not only littered with Cold War grotesqueriesâSartre and Beauvoir making a âdaily contributionâ to âthe enslavement of the satellite statesââbut with extraordinary philological howlers: Althusser, radical critic of Hegel, transmogrified into a âpassionate Hegelianâ; RĂ©gis Debray labelled a fellow-thinker of LĂ©vy and Glucksmann as a theorist of âtotalitarianismâ, rather than famously contemptuous of both the nouveaux philosophes and their theories.
Marxism and the French Left had, of course, a happy ending. Judt waxed lyrical about what he called Mitterrandâs âelectoral revolution of 1981â: after more than a century, French politics had finally been normalized. The new Parti Socialiste had broken out of its class, regional and religious ghettos; now a responsible reformist force, its only remaining task was to âacquire the political culture of a party of governmentâ like the Swedish or Austrian social democrats. Mitterrandâs victory was âa major turning point in French political history, of qualitatively greater significance than any hithertoâââfor the Socialists, 1981 was their finest hourâ. Not only had Mitterrand and his party âtransformed national politics in Franceâ, but they had firmly dissociated the left from âinternationalism and anti-militarismâ and could now be trusted on âdefenceâ.
The French historian
Judtâs first cycle of work, focused on France, comes to a close with Marxism and the French Left. How should it be assessed? Historiographically, the argument of Socialism in Provence is obviously superior to its successor. Franceâs industrialization was relatively slow in the nineteenth century; it had a large artisan and peasant sectorâstill almost half the population in 1945; yet it had introduced effective male suffrage as early as 1848. But such an account, linking political consciousness to class structure, raised a problem for Judt: it was too Marxian. Indeed his discomfort with it was clear even in Socialism in Provence where, after carefully establishing the link between peasantsâ economic interests and the emergence of socialism, he abruptly abandoned it, without theoretical or empirical motivation, to embrace a cultural explanation for the movementâs continuing appeal. Whatever the risk of conceptual incoherence, the switch was effective as a sort of historiographical cordon sanitaire, insulating twentieth-century France from class analysis.
Even hedged and sterilized, however, Socialism in Provenceâs attempt to link politics to class interests was beyond the pale in the mid-1980s, when Furet and his followers had entirely hegemonized the field. It was this, rather than any underlying intellectual problem, that surely explained Judtâs tacitly revised interpretation in Marxism and the French Left, so dramatically at odds with his first. Yet the central premise on which this new version rested, that late-nineteenth century France was a politically backward society, is patently false. Judt attempted to assimilate the French, Italian, and Spanish states of the period into the same type, but this did serious violence to their respective political histories. Universal male suffrage, for example, did not come to Italy until 1912, or Spain until 1931; it was definitively established in France by the 1880s. More importantly, France had created national representative institutions by the end of the eighteenth century, unlike any other large state on the European continent.
If Judt failed to provide a compelling historiographical explanation for the appeal of Marxism to a significant layer of French workers, peasants and intellectuals, what of his second argument: that its soft spot for marxisant precepts was responsible for the French leftâs lack of political success for most of the twentieth century? The issues here are complex, and Judtâs thinking far from consistent. Clarity requires first defining what âsuccessâ means. For Judt this was obvious enough: a ânormalâ social democracy. But it is unclear from a strictly historical point of view why this should be the standard. Judtâs doctoral thesis exemplifies the problem. One of the strengths of Reconstruction of the Socialist Party was its documentation of the broad ideological commitment to revolutionary socialism within the SFIO; Blum himself in the 1920s held that an âimpersonal dictatorship of the proletariatâ was an absolute necessity. But in that case, the historical question is not: why did the SFIO fail to act as a reformist social-democratic party, but rather: why did the SFIO fail to live up to its own self-understanding and act as a revolutionary party? Judt had evidently registered this problem in his first book, admitting that, in the 1920s, a programme of revolutionary transformation âdid not lack plausibilityâ; but he characteristically dismissed this line of thinking, on the grounds that even to ask such questions would be to apply a âlogicalâ rather than a historical standard.
Historiographically, of course, the reverse is the case: Judt himself was applying an abstracted âlogicalâ standard, in judging the inter-war SFIO from the perspective of post-war social democracy.
The political dĂ©nouement of Judtâs decade-long engagement with the history of the French left was his celebration of the Mitterrand era. But here too his analysis proved dud. According to hisâalbeit self-contradictoryâarguments, the ânormalizationâ of French politics in the 1980s, with Mitterrandâs victory and the elimination of the PCF as an electoral force, should have led at last to an effective social democracy. In fact, of course, Mitterrandâs legacy was the introduction of a gallicized Thatcherite neo-liberalism and, after 1990, abandonment of the last vestiges of Gaullist foreign policy for full participation in the new Atlantic order. Yet if Judtâs labours in the vineyard of French history produced decreasing historiographical or analytical rewards, his exposure to the methods of Furet and his disciples played a critical role in expanding his repertoire as a pro-Western polemicist. Handily, he would find in the âethical turnâ fashionable in late Cold War Paris a rhetorical stance and sententious tone that married perfectly with anti-Communist sermonizing. So, in Marxism and the French Left he explained:
To be a socialist today is to find oneself in one of two positions. On the one hand, you can be in favour of a generalized moral project which asserts itself in conscious defiance of capitalist (interest-related) priorities. Or else you must argue from a series of premises, stated or otherwise, which are still best characterized as âmarxismâ, and which entail firm commitment to certain propositions about the life span and self-destructive properties of capitalism.
Judt went on to lament: âit is the unwillingness of most socialists in France to think of themselves as engaged in a project of an essentially indeterminate and partial kind that prevents them adopting the first of the two approaches.â The secondâany theory of capitalism as a system with its own laws of motionâled, he asserted, straight to Soviet-style totalitarian Communism.
2. MANHATTAN
In the late 1980s, apparently bored by French history (and by his wife), Judt followed the trail blazed by Timothy Garton Ash and numerous others to Eastern Europe. Gorbachevâs diplomacy had removed any obstacles to humanitarian tourism and the region was now thoroughly penetrated by missionaries from the EEC and IMFâWorld Bank. A crash course in Czech, and meetings with Michnik, Havel and Kis, equipped Judt to present his credentials to Washington in the form of a paper given at the Wilson Center in 1987, âThe Politics of Impotence?â. From the vantage point of 2009, Judt would explain Czechoslovakia as his Mitteleuropa destination of choice in terms of its edgier national-cultural stereotype: âthat distinctly Polish (or Russian) sense of cultural grandeur was precisely what I wanted to circumnavigate, preferring the distinctively Czech qualities of doubt, cultural insecurity, and sceptical self-mockery.â At the time, however, his justification had been exactly the opposite: for Czechoslovakians, Judt suggested in 1987, âthe whole point of intellectual production is to bear moral witnessâ. Freedâas the interrogative ironization of the title tried to indicateâfrom any concrete political engagement by the force of circumstance, intellectuals like Havel answered to a higher âmoral responsibilityâ, just as Judt had told French socialists to do. âThe Politics of Impotence?â reported that, since 1968, oppositional Marxism in Eastern Europe had been replaced by a healthy focus on ârightsâ. Nevertheless, it warned, âto the extent that socialism is associated with a variety of welfare provisions, social-security systems and guarantees, a âreturnâ to capitalism would not be regarded with favour by most people.â
Judtâs re-location to the French Institute at New York University took place the same year, 1987. Shortly after, he scooped a $20 million bequest from the 80-year-old Manhattan socialite and former Ziegfeld Follies star Paulette Goddard, who had accumulated a fortune in the course of several marriages (Charlie Chaplin, Burgess âThe Penguinâ Meredith, Erich Maria Remarque). NYUâs Remarque Institute would open its doors in the late 90s, under Judtâs direction. In the meantime, he produced a further reworking of his thoughts on post-war French intellectuals: published in 1993, Past Imperfect: French Intellectuals, 1944â1956 was coolly received by specialist scholars but garnered fawning reviews for the director of the Remarque Institute in the key power-and-prestige outlets of the American academy; it also won Judt his first commission from the New York Review of Books.
To return once again to the subject of the post-war rive gauche might appear to have been flogging a dead horse, especially now that the Cold War had ended. But Judt seems to have felt that Marxism and the French Left had dealt with Sartre and his contemporaries too much in terms of French politics. Nowâand with little further reading requiredâhe would lambast their record in the larger global struggle of freedom against Communism, at greater length and brandishing loftier, if still ill-defined, concepts: justice, responsibility, morality and ethics. The Berlin Wall had fallen, but it still remained to extirpate any lingering trace of left-wing ideas. In France, a rabid anti-Sartrean literature had been accumulating since the late 1970s but little of it had yet appeared in English. Casting himself as a courageous moralist, Judt recycled its tropesâprincipally, that Sartre and Beauvoir were Stalinist apologistsârejecting any mere âneutral historicist accountâ: âIn seeking to explain something that is intrinsically unattractive, to which the reader would normally respond with distaste, one is not excused from the obligation to be accurate, but neither is one under a compelling obligation to pretend neutrality.â
Here, still more openly than in his previous work, Judt spurned any serious discussion of his subjectsâ thought: âThis book is neither a history of ideas nor a social history of French intellectualsâ; it is about âthe marked absence of a concern with public ethics or political moralityâ in Franceâwhich Judt quickly interpreted, before the reader had time to murmur Les mains sales, as: âwhy the French response to totalitarianism differed from that of intellectuals elsewhereâ. Although presented as an exercise in âa peculiarly Anglo-Saxon tradition of intellectual historyâ, the result had nothing to do with the Cambridge School; it was more like a posthumous contribution to the literature of the Congress for Cultural Freedom. Judt proceeded chiefly by undocumented assertion, anonymous attribution or conjunctive assimilationâtypically: âHow, in the face of all this evidence, could intelligent people wilfully defend communism as the hope of the future and Stalin as the solution to the riddle of History?ââas though any thorough-going critic of capitalism was also necessarily a worshiper of Stalin.
Sartreâs actual record on the Soviet Unionâthe criticisms of Stalinism in What is Literature, the excoriation of the camps and of the invasion of Hungary in Les Temps modernesâis simply scanted. âSartreâs philosophical thought during the 30s and early 40s was quite devoid of political and social implicationsâ, writes Judtâthe War Diaries? Being and Nothingness? âSartreâs contemporary opinions precluded any attention to questions of ethics or moralityââSaint Genet? Notebooks for an Ethics? The French radical tradition was âdominated by a combination of republican premises and Marxist projections, conflating the capacities of the state and the interests of the individualââbut wasnât Existentialism founded on the idea of radical individual freedom? âOne very special characteristic of the French style of thought has been the emphasis upon âtotalityâ, or the absoluteââunlike the Germans? There is a Gallic âdistaste for intellectual doubt, uncertainty or scepticismââDescartes?
Past Imperfectâs main argument, tirelessly reiterated, was that French left-wing intellectuals in this period lacked âany common ideal of justiceââalthough Judt also remarked at one point that there was no âconsensus about justiceâ in France as a whole, either; and indeed offered no conceptualization of his own. The result of this moral vacuum, he concluded, was to undermine French liberalism itself:
What was missing, then, in the political language of contemporary France were the central premises, the building blocks of a liberal political vision . . . Quite absent was the liberal assumption of a necessary and desirable space between the individual and the collective, the private and the public, society and the state.
By any measure Tocqueville, Constant and Guizot would appear rather substantial French liberal âbuilding blocksâ, constituting a richer tradition than that of nineteenth-century Britain, which produced little more than Mill. But it was the absence of a liberal âpolitical visionâ, not a theoretical tradition, that Judt was lamenting. Like the French left, liberalism in the Hexagon had also unfortunately âhistoricizedâ the moral idea of rights, by relating them to 1789. In sum, French liberals failed to grasp that liberalism is ânot about some sort of liberal project for society: it is about a society in which the messiness and openness of politics precludes the application of large-scale projects, however rational and ideal.â The âgeneralized moral projectâ that Judt had extolled seven years before, in Marxism and the French Leftââa project of an essentially indeterminate and partial kindââwas unceremoniously abandoned in Past Imperfect. Projects were now out; only the moral âvisionâ was now of value. (Indeed Judt appeared at this stage to have abandoned social democracy as well, preferring to speak of a more inclusive âliberalismâ.)
The intellectual configuration in France in the early 1990s was, of course, the very opposite of Judtâs representation of it. The liberalism of Furet and company was unquestionably the hegemonic ideology of the period. In a ludicrous inversion, Judt depicted it as the lonely, marginal thinking of a tiny minority, allowing him to offer his own thoroughly conventional book as aâtacitly, braveâcontribution to heterodoxy, along with theirs. But politically, Past Imperfect suggested that, just as, even after Mitterrand, French social democracy could never quite come up to British or Nordic standards, so French liberals were âunable to commit themselves to the utilitarian or ethical individualism of their British contemporariesâ in the nineteenth century, and even today âfew thinkers in France have so far undertaken to construct a moral vocabulary for liberal politics, an ethics, so to speak, of democracy.â Even with the PCF banished to the fringes, France remained insufficiently Anglo-Saxon.
Pantheon
Judtâs next book returned to the subject of French intellectuals, this time focused not on his villains, but on his heroes. The Burden of Responsibility: Blum, Camus, Aron and the French Twentieth Century appeared in 1998, dedicated, appropriately enough, to the memory of François Furet. Once again, Judt paid little attention to his subjectsâ ideas: according to Burden of Responsibility, Blum made no contribution to socialist theory, Camus was unpolitical, Aron overvalued philosophy. Judt explained that this was a study of political âresponsibilityâ, in contrast to the analysis of political âirresponsibilityâ in his previous book. His three exemplars, Blum, Camus and Aron, stood out against the three âintersecting forms of irresponsibilityââpolitical, moral and intellectualâthat âshaped French public life from the end of the First World War until the middle of the 1970sâ. Indeed the irresponsibility of French intellectuals had expanded considerably since Past Imperfect, when they had at least, according to Judt, seen themselves as responsible to history, if not to other people. But what did the two contrasting terms actually mean? The Burden of Responsibility provides a distinctly unhelpful tautology, defining âirresponsibilityâ as âthe propensity in various spheres of public life to neglect or abandon intellectual, moral or political responsibilityâ. Judt clarifies: âIn addition to the qualities of courage and integrity, Blum, Aron, and Camus have something else in common. They were all anti-Communists.â As the New York Times reviewer of Past Imperfect had laconically remarked, Judtâs idea of a responsible intellectual was simply one whose views he found sympathetic.
If Judt had no difficulty establishing the âabsolute clarity on the Communist questionâ of his trio, he systematically downplayed their complicity with imperialism. Yet Blumâs first act, as a chef de cabinet in the 1914 Union SacrĂ©e government, was to betray the Socialistsâ solemn pre-war promise not to participate in the mutual slaughter of the Great War. In 1925, at the height of the Rif colonial war, he informed the Assembly that there was ânot only a right, but a duty for what are known as the superior races to draw towards themselves the races which have not attained the same degree of culture and civilisationâ. Becoming Prime Minister again in December 1945, four weeks after the bombardment of Haiphong that launched the French war in Indochina, he explained that the colonial mission of France was ânot yet accomplishedâ. Camus, who said virtually nothing about the war in Indochina, was dismissed even by Aron as no more than âa well-intentioned colonizerâ in Algeria. Both Camus and Aron approved the Anglo-French-Israeli aggression against Egypt in 1956, Aron warning of the âFĂŒhrer on the Nileâ and Camus of the menace of Soviet-backed âArab imperialismâ. Aron himself backed both the French and the American wars in Indochina, and objected to the French war in Algeria not on ethical grounds but because the French civilizing mission, however laudable in itself, âwould be unsustainably expensiveâ. When asked why he never spoke out against French torture in Algeria, Aron replied that he had never known anyone speak in favour of torture, so what was the point? Judt appears to be perfectly satisfied with this example of moral responsibility, whose logic is that the subject need never have been mentioned.
An allusion to Weberâs classic discussion of the ethics of responsibility illustrated Judtâs tenuous grasp of the complex issues raised by this highly charged term. The âWeberian calculusâ, as he glossed it, entailed âthe sense that we can behave responsibly without making partisan commitmentsâor else that a partisan engagement may under certain circumstances be the responsible optionâ. Weberâs actual view was rather different. For the great sociologist, the ethic of responsibility was embodied by the political actor who took responsibility for the use of âlegitimate violenceâ. He warned, in âPolitics as a Vocationâ, that âWhomsoever contracts with violent meansâand every politician doesâis exposed to its specific consequences.â Ultimately, the political figure faced a choice between one way of using violence and another, without an adequate standard for discriminating between them; to act politically, then, required an absolute belief in the rightness of oneâs own cause, in order to transcend the chasm between political ends and means. An ethic of conviction and an ethic of responsibility were not âabsolute contrasts, but rather supplementsâ. Indeed, Weberâs concept of political responsibility here was not far from Sartreâs view, a fact that Judt naturally does not confront. As Sartre put the point, in his long essay in Les Temps modernes following the Hungarian revolution:
In the worst case, the assumption of a moral position disguises the operation of a politician; in the best it does not affect the facts and the moralist misses the point. But politics, of whatever sort, is an action undertaken in common with certain men against other men.
Both Sartre and Weber refused the comfortable stance of the moralizer because they were aware of the tension between ethics and politics, and did not try to obscure it with high-sounding bromides.
3. EUROPE
By the mid-90s the New York Review of Books was offering Judt a more prominent platform, as publicist and commentator, than scholarly work could provide. After his first appearance there in August 1993, reviewing a work on the fate of French Jews under the Vichy regime, Judt became a regular fixture, contributing three or four pieces a year over the next decade. Eventually he would rival, or even overtake, Garton Ash and Buruma in his frequency as a quasi-editorialist, pronouncing not just on France but on Eastern Europe, the lessons of the Cold War and the fate of the West in general. The year 1993 also saw his first contribution to The New Republic: an attack on Althusser, âthe Paris stranglerâ. He would soon join the magazineâs editorial board. The posture Judt had developed in the course of his assaults on the French leftâtailing-ending the liberal-establishment vanguard, while portraying himself as a courageous exception, a lone moral voiceâserved him well within this wider field. In 1995â96, as Clinton and Albright elbowed aside Kohl and Mitterrand to knock ex-Yugoslav heads together, Judt lamented the failure of European leadership. In 1997, as the prophets of the Third Way took up residence in Downing Street, he called for a new social-liberal agenda. He lauded Blairâs âfirm and honourable standâ on Kosovo and endorsed the Oslo Accords on Palestine. In The New Republic he contributed to a 1997 âZionism at 100â symposiumâarguing that Zionism should not be seen as an ethno-nationalist movement, but a universalist-enlightenment oneâand attacked Peter Novickâs critique of the instrumentalization of the Judeocide in The Holocaust in American Life.
In 2008 Judt would publish a selection of these writings in Reappraisals, appointing himself as a memorializer to the contemporary world on the lessons of âthe forgotten twentieth centuryâ; such overlooked themes as vigilance against Communism and Holocaust recognition taking pride of place. In his Introduction, Judt regretted that the term âintellectualâ had come to evoke a ânarrow band of left-leaning âprogressivesââ, with Sartre at their head, rather than his own pantheon: Camus, Koestler and Ko?akowski. Judtâs paean to the last, in keeping with his general approach to the history of ideas, managed to avoid any mention of Ko?akowskiâs religious conversion, inconvenient for Judt as a sharp critic of Woytila.
Unsurprisingly, perhaps, Judtâs historical research took a back seat during this period. His only book between 1993 and 2005 was a slender volume containing three lectures, two of them already published in the NYRB, which appeared as A Grand Illusion? An Essay on Europe in 1996. No rationale was provided for the switch from French socialism to the larger, more nebulous subject of âEuropeâ as a historical subject. In his NYRB obituary, Timothy Snyderâdemonstrating an astonishing ignorance of his colleagueâs actual trajectoryâwould suggest that it was Judtâs âmidlife participation in Eastern European intellectual life, which hastened the break with Marxism [sic] and enabled a more capacious view of the continent.â But although he liked to term himself an âEastern Europeanistâ, Judt never produced any monograph on the region; even his 1987 âA Politics of Impotence?â remained a working paper.
The political tone of A Grand Illusion? was distinctly Euro-pessimist: âa truly united Europe is sufficiently unlikely for it to be unwise and self-defeating to insist on itâ. The exceptionally favourable combination of circumstances that drove European integration forward up to the 1980s would not reappear:
These were unrepeatable, one-time transformations. That is to say, Western Europe will probably never again have to catch up on thirty years of economic stagnation or half a century of agrarian depression, or rebuild after a disastrous war. Nor will it be bound together by the need to do so, or by the coincidence of Communist threat and American encouragement.
Extension to the East could not occur on the terms granted to existing member states, since this would require huge transfer payments from Western European economies already suffering from persistent unemployment and slow growth. Long-running economic divergences between the two halves of Europe, dating back to before 1914, constituted a major obstacle to unification. Moreover, the lessons of Yugoslaviaâthis was written at the moment of the Dayton Accordsâillustrated âthe weakness of European initiatives, the compulsion to avoid engagement and the absence of any recognized collective strategic interest beyond maintaining the status quoâ. âIn its strong formâ, Judt concluded, âthe idea of Europe has had its day.â
Cause célÚbre
At the turn of the century, commentary in the NYRB and New Republic continued to claim much of Judtâs time. His response to 9.11 announced that the world had crossed the threshold into a new moral-political universe. He rallied immediately behind the war in Afghanistan and organized an October 2002 conference on the central war-on-terror theme of âglobal anti-Americanismâ. Like millions of others, however, he was dubious about Bush and Cheneyâs plans for the invasion of Iraq; also about the salience of the settlersâ agenda in Israeli politics. In July 2002 he wrote a piece mildly critical of âintolerant, ultra-religiousâ settlers and anti-Arab mizrahi Israelis in The New Republic. The following year his NYRB article, âIsrael: The Alternativeâ, created a furore in New York. As Judt would recall, âthe rabbis of Riversideâ picketed a talk he was due to give at a local high school, marshalling protesters dressed as concentration-camp inmates. The event says more about the thuggishness of hardline American Zionists than it does about Judtâs essay, which recycled the venerable notion of a bi-national democracy for IsraelâPalestine.
The Oslo process was now over, Judt declared: âIsrael continues to mock its American patron, building illegal settlements in general disregard of the âroad mapâ.â The US president had been âreduced to a ventriloquistâs dummy, pitifully reciting the Israeli cabinetâs line: âItâs all Arafatâs faultâ.â Palestinian Arabs, âcorralled into bantustansâ, subsisted on EU handouts. Sharon, Arafat and a handful of terrorists could all âclaim victoryâ. Departing from his previous assertion that Zionism had been a universalist movement, he declared it a typical late-nineteenth-century ethno-nationalist one, and as such an anachronism in âa world that has moved on, a world of individual rights, open frontiers and international lawâ. Given the demographic trend towards a Palestinian majority in âgreater Israelâ, the country would now have to choose between being a non-democratic ethno-religious state, with a growing majority of disenfranchised non-Jews, or a multi-cultural, multi-ethnic secular democracy. Israel was already âa multi-cultural society in all but nameâ, yet ranked its citizens according to ethno-religious criteria. Furthermore, âIsraelâs behaviour has been a disaster for American foreign policyâââWashingtonâs unconditional support for Israel even in spite of (silent) misgivings is the main reason why most of the world no longer credits our good faithâ:
It is now tacitly conceded by those in a position to know that Americaâs reasons for going to war in Iraq were not necessarily those advertised at the time. For many in the current US Administration, a major consideration was the need to destabilize and then reconfigure the Middle East in a manner thought favourable to Israel.
Formerly, the existence of the state of Israel had allowed Jews to âwalk tallâ. Now, howeverâthe actual tipping-point is not specifiedâits behaviour left non-Israeli Jews âexposed to criticism and vulnerable to attack for things they didnât doâââthe depressing truth is that Israel today is bad for the Jewsâ. The situation had corroded American domestic debate: âRather than think straight about the Middle East, American politicians and pundits slander our European allies when they dissent, speak glibly and irresponsibly of resurgent anti-Semitism when Israel is criticized and censoriously rebuke any public figure at home who tries to break from the consensusââJudt apparently forgetting his own censorious rebuke of Novick a few years before. The volte face on Israel led to Judtâs ejection from The New Republicâs editorial board and a rabid riposte from his former friend Leon Wieseltier, its literary editor, who pointed out accurately enough that the idea of a one-state solution, far from requiring anyone to âthink the unthinkableâ, as Judt had written, was a notion as old as the conflict over Palestine itself.
Judt did not include the Israel essay in his 2008 collection Reappraisals and seems scarcely to have addressed the one-state solution again. But reckless neo-conservative interventionism and the crudity of right-wing American Zionism had clearly soured him on the society of which he was now a citizen. In early 2005 the NYRB published Judtâs âThe Good Society: Europe vs Americaâ, which strongly favoured the former. A few months later Postwar, his 900-page history of Europe since 1945, appeared. The idea of writing on the 1945â89 period had apparently come to Judt in December 1989, within a month of the fall of the Berlin Wall: âthe history of post-war Europe would need to be rewrittenââin retrospect, the epoch would seem âa post-war parenthesis, the unfinished business of a conflict that ended in 1945 but whose epilogue had lasted for another half centuryâ. In the event, Past Imperfect, A Grand Illusion? and book reviewing had intervened. By the time the book came to be written, Judtâs view of Europe had undergone a dramatic revision.
Exemplary Europe
For the most part, Postwar offered a familiar narrative of the period, somewhat meandering in structure and largely focused on the West; coverage of Eastern Europe mostly functioned as a sombre counterpoint to the main melody. Opening with a survey of the state of Europe after World War Two, the book covered the onset of Cold War, the advent of western affluence and the âsocial democratic momentâ; the 1960s, East and West; accelerated EEC integration, as a response to 1970s economic turbulence; the new Hayekian ârealismâ of the 1980s, in both Thatcherite and mitterrandiste forms; Solidarno??, Gorbachev and the fall of the Comecon regimes in 1989; German reunification, Maastricht, the break-up of Yugoslavia and EU expansion. Into this lengthy, often rather flat account, Judt inserted what he confessed was âan avowedly personal interpretationâ. Post-war Europe, he argued, had produced not just the integrated structures of the EU but a social model that stood as a moral âbeaconâ to aspirant members and a âglobal challengeâ to the American way of life. Europe had emerged, at the dawn of the twenty-first century, as a âparagon of the international virtuesâ:
a community of values and a system of inter-state relations held up by Europeans and non-Europeans alike as an exemplar for all to emulate. In part this was the backwash of growing disillusion with the American alternative; but the reputation was well earned . . . Neither America nor China had a serviceable model to propose for universal emulation. In spite of the horrors of their recent pastâand in large measure because of themâit was Europeans who were now uniquely placed to offer the world some modest advice on how to avoid repeating their own mistakes. Few would have predicted it sixty years before, but the twenty-first century might yet belong to Europe.
Judtâs argument might be read as a grand narrative for todayâs Eurocracy, analogous to the uplifting national tales of the early twentieth century, such as Volpeâs Italia in Cammino or Marshallâs Our Island Story. His aim seems to have been to produce a synthesis of his now-revived admiration for social democracy and his hopes for the EU as an alternative to Bushâs America. The âEuropean social modelâ became the new pole of attraction for Judtâs politics: more acceptable than the neo-conservative US and less passĂ© than the labour movement itself. But the attempt to conflate European integration, the post-war welfare state and the record of the social-democratic parties into an exemplar for the twenty-first century ended in analytical incoherence. Postwar oscillated continually between the assertion that âwelfare capitalismâ was non-partisan, âtruly post-ideologicalâ, and the claim that it was a quintessentially social-democratic creation. On the one hand, the welfare state was the result of a âdeep longing for normalityâ produced by the inter-war age of extremes and the lessons of World War Two. For the generation of 1945, âsome workable balance between political freedoms and the rational, equitable distributive function of the administrative state seemed the only sensible route out of the abyssâ. This meant âa broad consensus not to press inherited ideological or cultural divisions to the point of political polarizationâ and a âde-politicized citizenryâ, capped by âreform-mindedâ Christian Democrat parties and âa parliamentary Leftâ. On the other hand, welfare capitalism was the âdistinctive visionâ of social democracy, which held that âgenuine improvements in the condition of all classes could be obtained in incremental and peaceful waysâ.
Judt drives home the importance of a social-democratic party to final outcomes by contrasting Scandinavia and Eastern Europe. The reason that Sweden, in particular, did not develop in the same way as âother economically depressed societies on the European margin between the warsâ was due to the Social Democrats. By renouncing âradical dogma and revolutionary ambitionsâ, the Swedish sad was able to incorporate small-holding peasants and strike a deal with Swedish capital at Saltsjöbaden in 1938. More generally:
The embittered and destitute peasants of inter-war central and southern Europe formed a ready constituency for Nazis, Fascists or single-issue Agrarian populists. But the equally troubled farmers, loggers, crofters and fishermen of Europeâs far north turned in growing numbers to the Social Democrats, who actively supported agrarian cooperatives . . . and thereby blurred the longstanding socialist distinctions between private production and collectivist goals, âbackwardâ country and âmodernâ town that were so electorally disastrous in other countries.
The notion of a peasant-based social democracy as the road not taken in inter-war Eastern Europe is, of course, completely unhistorical. Agriculture there was profoundly backward at the time; when popular uprisings weakened landed elites, as happened in Romania, the underlying organization of production tended to revert back to subsistence farming. The agrarian economy simply did not produce adequate surpluses for a sustained modernization drive. This was one reason for the similarity among the modernizing political movements there: liberal, fascist or Communist, all faced the basic problem of extracting sufficient surplus from the peasant sector to industrialize. The choice in Eastern Europe was never really between social democracy and Leninism, but among structurally similar modernizing regimes with different ideological labels. The situation in Scandinavia, particularly in Sweden, was entirely different: a substantial free-holder peasantry existed there, literacy was widespread and agrarian surpluses were much higher. Peasants were never âequally troubledâ in Scandinavia. In general, regional social democracy operated in such a uniquely favourable environment that it was never available as a model for export, as most of its leaders recognized.
Judtâs argument in Postwar further oscillated between claims that the welfare state has been in serious danger since the 1970s and declarations that it was the cornerstone of the twenty-first-century European social model. The first argument, based on a decidedly sketchy political economyânot a strong suit for Judt, as Postwar showedâclaimed that, by the early 1970s, the profit margins that had made the social-democratic class compromise possible came under threat, as the âmigration of surplus agricultural labour into productive urban industryâ had ended and ârates of productivity increase began inexorably to declineâ; Keynesian stimulus policies created inflation while failing to generate growth. Furthermore, the âwhite, male, employed working classâ, whose social-democratic parties had spearheaded the welfare state, was starting to contract. On the other hand, Judt claimed that it had survived robustly through all the ideological and political din about it. âEconomic liberalization did not signal the fall of the welfare state, nor even its terminal decline, notwithstanding the hopes of its theorists. It did, though, illustrateââstrange choice of verbââa seismic shift in the allocation of resources and initiative from public to private sectors.â
Postwarâs paean to the European social model stood in striking contrast to the gloomy outlook of A Grand Illusion?, which received no mention. The two books also offered sharply different accounts of Europeâs eastâwest divide. In 1995, Judt had disputed the notion that the division was âan artificial creation of the Cold War, an iron curtain gratuitously and recently drawn across a single cultural space.â On the contrary, as early as the fifteenth century there had been âan invisible line that already ran from north to south through the middle of Europe.â To extend EU membership to the ex-Communist European countries would be âan act of charityâ. Without a word of explanation, Postwar reverses these claims: the division is entirely a creation of the Cold War; before World War Two, âthe differences between North and South, rich and poor, urban and rural, counted for more than those between East and West.â After 1945, however:
The effect of the Sovietization of Eastern Europe was to draw it steadily away from the western half of the continent. Just as Western Europe was about to enter an era of dramatic transformation and unprecedented prosperity, Eastern Europe was slipping into a coma: a winter of inertia and resignation, punctured by cycles of protest and subjugation, that would last for nearly four decades.
In this reading, the advance of the Soviet glacis had blocked the regionâs chance of establishing an indigenous welfare state. Judtâs contrary argument in âPolitics of Impotence?ââthat central Europeans were so attached to their statesâ welfare provisions that they might not look kindly on the restoration of capitalismâhad evidently been forgotten.
Judtâs encomium to the European social model is further undermined by the second, less tendentious strand of his narrative: a rather humdrum account of European integration. As a historian, Judt had little talent for bringing protagonists to lifeâindeed, little interest in character as suchâand Postwar offered no fresh interpretation or archival discoveries. Yet the bare facts it presented on the transnational agreements that eventually produced the EU showed that, whatever one might say about the European social model, it was a historical theme quite independent from that of European union. None of the key stages on the path to integration had much to do with the welfare state; they were mostly the result of geo-political calculations and, from the late 1980s, basically neo-liberal. The 1950 Schuman Plan had allowed Germany to escape from Allied economic controls, while providing a guarantee to the French against German re-armament. As Judt himself pointed out, the European Economic Community was an attempt to open French and German markets, again for largely political reasons. The impetus towards establishing a European monetary system came from an attempt to stabilize exchange rates, after the collapse of the Bretton Woods system. The creation of the European Union, through the 1987 Single European Act and 1992 Maastricht Treaty, established the free circulation of goods, services and capital among its members but also imposed harsh German-style budgetary requirements. As Postwar noted, Eurozone finance ministers would be âunable to respond to the Siren-calls of voters and politicians for easier money and increased public spendingâ.
Judt attempted to resolve this tension between the actual dynamics of European integration and his supposed European social model through some implausible rhetorical linkagesâfor example:
In relative terms, the so-called âsocialâ element in the EU budget was tinyâless than 1 percent of gnp. But from the late Eighties, the budgets of the European Community and the Union nevertheless had a distinctively redistributive quality, transferring resources from wealthy regions to poor ones and contributing to a steady reduction in the aggregate gap between rich and poor: substituting in effect, for the nationally based Social-Democratic programmes of an earlier generation.
This was to confuse wish with reality. Judt himself pointed out twenty pages later that regional and social inequalities in Europe had sharply increased since the 1980s: a small super-rich core now contrasted with the poorer regions of the Mediterranean zone and Eastern Europe. Rather than scaling up a welfarist model, European integration had if anything undermined it.
What of the âsocial modelâ itself? Judt suggested that, in sharp contrast to the United States, European societies were marked by high taxes, long vacations, free healthcare, good public education and high life expectancy. But the relation between this ideal and actually existing European societies remained unclear. Mostly Judt seemed to be imagining a loose conceptual average of Europeâs rich northwestâBelgium, Denmark, Britain, Ireland, France, Germany, Norwayârather than the uneven social topography of the continent as a whole. Although they were discussed in passing in Postwar, the unequal societies of Europeâs south and eastâPortugal, Spain, Italy, GrEECeâwere never allowed to impinge on its âsocial modelâ. Nor, finally, does Judtâs attempt to counter-pose a âgoodâ European model to a âbadâ American one stand up. As his own narrative made clear, post-war Europe was closely shaped by US interventionism; Washington took extraordinary measures to reconstruct Western Europeâs economies and to provide its states with a security guarantee that removed the need to rearm. Historically, the âEuropean modelâ, however specified, has never been an alternative to American hegemony, but rather a consequence of it.
4. SOCIAL DEMOCRACY?
The fragility of Judtâs attempted synthesis in Postwar was most evident in its rapid breakdown. By the time of his last book, Ill Fares the Land, he had undergone another conversion in political outlook. The book originated as a valedictory lecture at NYU in 2009, given after Judt had been diagnosed with amyotrophic lateral sclerosis. A transcription of the lecture had been published in the NYRB, bringing a âchorus of demands for its expansion into a little bookâ. The resulting political testament struck a declamatory note: âSomething is profoundly wrong with the way we live todayâââand yet we seem unable to conceive of alternativesâ. Ill Fares the Land sought to provide one, in the form of a rehabilitated social democracy. Alas for his admirers, the results contradicted or flatly reversed many of Judtâs most confident pronouncements on the welfare state and social democracy in Postwar. The resulting confusion was amply demonstrated in his attempts to grapple with four key questions.
(i) The welfare stateâwho created it?
Judt wanted to maintain once again that the welfare state was both the product of a cross-party âKeynesian consensusâ and a historic social-democratic achievement. But whereas Postwar had celebrated the superiority of Europeâs social model, Ill Fares the Land played down any such contrast, arguing instead that Rooseveltâs New Deal and Johnsonâs Great Society were in practice the American version of social democracy. The âlonging for normalityâ after World War Two that had explained Europeansâ special predilection for state-administered welfare in Postwar now apparently applied to Americans as well. A continual slippage in Judtâs use of the term âsocial democracyâ sometimes allowed it to suggest a form of Hegelian historical reason, an âobjectiveâ purpose that escapes the âsubjectiveâ intentions of those involved. Thus anyone who supported post-war Keynesian demand management gets promoted to the rank of âobjectiveâ social democratâand larded with praiseâwhatever his or her party label:
Not only did social democrats sustain full employment for nearly three decades, they also maintained growth rates more than competitive with those of the untrammelled market economies of the past. And on the back of these economic successes they introduced radically disjunctive social changes that came to seem, within a short span of years, quite normal. When Lyndon Johnson spoke of building a âgreat societyâ on the basis of massive public expenditure on a variety of government-sponsored programs and agencies, few objected and fewer still thought the proposition odd.
Supporters of Eugene McCarthyâindeed, LBJ himselfâmight be surprised at this retrospective elevation to the status of a Yankee Olof Palme.
Similarly, while Postwar had given pride of place to Scandinavian and British social democracy, Ill Fares the Land explained that âpureâ social democracy along Scandinavian lines had always been ânon-exportableâ, while the welfare state created by post-war British Labour was not really social democratic at all, but simply âpragmaticâ. Accompanying this was a much more pronounced emphasis on the non-radicalism of the welfare state, now not just âpost-ideologicalâ, as in Postwar, but the creation of âinstinctive conservativesâ. By Judtâs criteria, indeed, Berlusconi, Sarkozy and Merkel might count as social democrats:
Social democracy, in one form or another, is the prose of contemporary European politics. There are very few European politicians, and fewer still in positions of influence, who would dissent from core social democratic assumptions about the duties of the state, however much they might differ as to their scope.
The conceptual muddiness of this approach, in which virtually all political actors become the unwitting instruments of a social-democratic Geist, succeeds only in obscuring the central political and historical issues: what was the actual role of social-democratic parties in the construction of the welfare state, and what part was played by broader political-economic conditions? These were questions that Judt never even posed. Two essential components to any answer might be stressed, though: firstly, the long economic boom of the post-war period, which has little if any linkage to the strength of social-democratic parties but whose arc tracks the expansion of welfarism very closely. Secondly, the existence of a rival Communist bloc, proclaiming itself the homeland of the workers. The conversion of social-democratic parties into neo-liberal centre lefts followed the decline and fall of the state-socialist challenge. Judt, the life-long anti-Communist, at one point lets this slip himself:
That is why the fall of Communism mattered so much. With its collapse, there unravelled the whole skein of doctrines that had bound the Left together for over a century. However perverted the Muscovite variation, its sudden and complete disappearance could not but have a disruptive impact on any party or movement calling itself âsocial democraticâ . . . for the Left, the absence of a historically buttressed narrative leaves an empty space.
However one defines the relationship, empirically it seems clear that social democracy has been deeply dependent on its revolutionary twin. The attempt to formulate a social-democratic politics in the absence of a socialist one would seem historically implausible.
(ii) The welfare stateâwhat went wrong?
Without explanation, the boosterism of Postwar, in which the European social model had been a beacon to the world, turned to cassandrism in Ill Fares the Land, which saw the welfare state as disastrously eroded by rising inequality and declining public services. Judt focused chiefly on the US and UK, but made clear that not even Sweden, France, Germany or the Netherlands had been exempt from negative developments. What explained this deterioration? Principally, Judt argued, it was the fault of the generation that had grown up under the post-war welfare state and had taken the security it gave them for granted, becoming disaffected instead of grateful: âthe narcissism of the student movements, new Left ideologues and the popular culture of the 60s generation invited a conservative backlashâ, allowing the Right to roll forward the âintellectual revolutionâ mounted by Hayek and Friedman, imposing a free-market dogmatics on the political sceneâan outcome that was âfar from inevitableâ.
For Judt, the crisis of the welfare state was therefore largely a matter of ideasâselfish ones on the part of the 60s radicals, and counter-arguments that were âforceful indeedâ from the Hayekians. If things had been otherwise, the post-war consensus would presumably still be intact. What was striking was the complete absence of any economic explanation of the crisis in the âKeynesian consensusâ around Judtâs welfare state. Where economic changes received any mention, it was always as an aside. Thus: âAs the post-war boom wound downââno explanation of why it did soâunemployment rose and the tax-base of the state was threatened. Or: âOnly when the welfare state began to run into difficultiesââunexplainedâdid neo-liberal ideas take hold. Or: âThe growth in unemployment over the course of the 1970sâ and âthe inflation of those yearsââunexplainedâput new strains on the exchequer. Although the crisis of welfarism was the central topic in Ill Fares the Land, there was even less material explanation of it than in Postwar.
(iii) Social Democracy: success or failure?
Overlapping with Judtâs account of welfarism was his depiction of the fate of social democracy, tacitly understood as parties of the Socialist International. Were they the vehicle for a renewed welfare state? Judt mentioned in passing a variety of partly contradictory causes for their âloss of nerveâ: a shrinking working class; the fall of Communism; the fact that social democracy âin one form or anotherâ had become so generalizedââthe prose of contemporary European politicsâ, as aboveâthat the parties themselves now had little distinctive to offer. But Judt could not afford to let such gloomy reflections go too far, lest they undermine the purpose of his bookâa ringing call to revive social democracy as the last best hope of the age. The resulting sermon contradicted itself at every step. Thus, by the end of the twentieth century, social democracy had not merely âfulfilled many of its long-standing objectivesâ, but âsucceeded beyond the wildest dreams of its foundersââthough presumably Judt was not here referring to Marx, Engels, Bebel, Bernstein. Yet in that case, why was the land faring so ill? Or again: a âdefensive stance made senseâ for social democracy, to âconvince voters that it was a respectable radical choice within a liberal polityâ. Yet âsocial democracy cannot just be about preserving worthy institutions as a defence against worse optionsâ.
(iv) What is to be done?
Success or failure, however, for the moment social democracy had âlost its wayâ. What was needed to put it back on the right track? Judtâs answer was a ne plus ultra of vapid idealism: it was a better kind of language that would change the world. For the problem of contemporary social democracy was ânot what to doâ [sic] but âhow to talk about itâââour disability is discursive: we simply do not know how to talk about these things any moreâ. Ill Fares the Land harped on this theme from the start, as Judt pondered how to answer a twelve-year-old who had warned him that the word âsocialismâ was toxic in the us; Judtâs solution was to tell the boy to forget âsocialismâ and think instead of âsocial democracyâ, with its wholesome âacceptance of capitalismâ.
A ânew language of politicsâ was, of course, the thesis of Furetâs Rethinking the French Revolution, in which society more or less levitated by the sheer magic of words. But Judt gave a characteristically British twist to this French conception: the discourse that would rescue social democracy was a âmoral narrativeâ, though Judt did not explain what such a narrative might say. Combined with this was a call to rehabilitate the state, as âthe only institution standing between individuals and non-state actors like banks or international corporationsââthough since Judt did not specify what the state should do, the effect was little more than rhetorical. Judt was, of course, very ill at the time. Nevertheless, it boggles the mind to think that a serious observer of current affairs living in the United States could in 2010 describe the âstateâ as a neutral third party, standing between banks and individuals. This was the political order that socialized the massive bank losses of 2008 against widespread popular rage. The discontinuity of style and personnel between Bush and Obama has only underscored the fundamental continuity of state policy toward the banks. Ill Fares the Land concluded with a desperately bland set of political prescriptions. âIncremental improvements upon unsatisfactory circumstances are the best we can hope for, and all we should seek.â With full allowance made for the conditions in which he was working at this stageâthe nightmare of his advancing paralysis vividly described in the pages of the NYRB âin Judtâs final testament, neo-social democracy remains remarkably insipid.
Assessment
How do the accolades for Judt as a âgreat historianâ, âfearless criticâ and âbrilliant political commentatorâ stand up against a cool examination of his work? As historiography, even his earliest, most substantial scholarly works on FranceâReconstruction of the Socialist Party and Socialism in Provenceâwere weakened by the aggressive tendentiousness of his approach. Marxism and the French Left and Past Imperfect were avowedly selective and polemical. Judt lacked the most basic requirement for any student of intellectual history: the ability to grasp and reconstruct an idea with philological precision. His lack of interest in ideas is borne out in extenso throughout his copious writings on intellectuals: there were never any serious attempts to reconstruct a thinkerâs position, so as to probe and question it. Even summaries of figures to whom he was well-disposed were slapdash; writers to whom he was hostile were regularly excoriated for views they did not hold. Judged as an intellectual historian, the verdict on Judt must be negative. His magnum opus, Postwar, is regularly listed for undergraduate European History courses. But its 900 pages produced little new by way of evidence or interpretationâa weakness underlined by the absence of even the most minimal scholarly apparatus, beyond a âgeneral bibliographyâ available from NYU.
Judt himself confessed in his final interview that at school he had been considered âbetter at literature than historyâ; also bragging, âI wasâand knew I wasâamong the best speakers and writers of my age cohort. I donât mean I was the best historianâ. In effect, it was his talent, limited but real, as a polemicist and a pamphleteer that disqualified Judt as a historian of ideas, much as he liked to claim the loftier calling. His range as a polemicist was relatively narrow: there is a limit to what can be got from attacking the French left or lauding fellow defenders of the Free World. His negative judgements on political leadersâThatcher, Bush, Clinton, Blairâcarried little analytical heft; his belated criticism of Israelâs West Bank settlements never explained at what point the Zionist project had gone wrong. Nevertheless, judged as a polemicist, the verdict can be more favourable, exonerating Judt of the heedless inconsistencies, both conceptual and analytic, that marred his work as historian of Europe and latter-day champion of neo-social democracy. A pamphleteer may be allowedâeven expectedâto change his views more or less at the drop of a hat. If the EU is now a moral beacon to the world, now a sad example of failed leadership; or the welfare state now the legacy of organized labour, now the common sense of capitalist politiciansâso what? All grist to the mill. A historian will be held to different standards.